The Shape of the Universe

The problem

The universe exists in space and time. Decades before Einstein, writers such as Gustav Fechner (under the pen-name of Dr. Mises) and CH Hinton proposed that Time was a dimension and that the underlying fabric of reality was a four-dimensional "spacetime". Based on a idea by Henri Poincaré, Hermann Minkowski proposed a mathematical description of spacetime, now known as Minkowski space, in which time was treated as an imaginary variable. (In this context it is crucial to realise that "imaginary" is just a technical mathematical term, in much the some way that mathematicians talk of "irrational" numbers which are in fact perfectly reasonable. Stay grounded!)

Einstein seized on Minkowski's spacetime to express his theory of relativity. However his General Relativity introduced a complication, in that spacetime was forced into curves by the presence of matter and energy, it was no longer the kind of "flat" infinite space such as the Euclidean space taught in schools. His equations showed broadly how space would curve under certain circumstances, but did not offer a unique solution for the actual universe. For example if there was enough matter present, then spacetime would close up on itself in the way that the surface of a ball does, with no boundary. On the other hand, if there was insufficient matter then spacetime could extend on outwards indefinitely and never end.

The problem is that there are a huge number of shapes that such a spacetime can take, referred to rather abstractly as "solutions to the equations of General Relativity." We do not know which of all these possibilities is the real one. We get glimpses of their properties, such as whether a particular one is expanding or shrinking in space over time. But these glimpses miss most of the reality.

The study of such curved spaces and their overall shapes is called topology, and the various-shaped spaces are called manifolds. A manifold is the idea of a two-dimensional surface, generalised to allow more dimensions. Where space can be thought of as a three-dimensional manifold, spacetime is a four-dimensional one. Such manifolds may be twisted in amazing ways and may or may not have boundaries. For example the outer surface of a ball has no boundaries, while the outer surface of a bottle has a boundary around its rim and a length of pipe has two boundaries, one at each end.

Often it is convenient to lay down some kind of coordinate system over the manifold, so that we can use the techniques of analytic geometry to describe it. For example the surface of the Earth is a sphere, a particular kind of two-dimensional manifold. We customarily lay down lines of latitude and longitude so that we can draw maps or charts, measure distances and angles, and navigate from one place to another, with a complete set of charts collected into an atlas. Such a coordinate system must have a scale or metric with an origin and orientation. But there is no absolute coordinate system, we have to choose one. For centuries nations such as France, Britain, Russia and China all used different systems. In the end, you pick the coordinate system that is most useful to you at the time, and you may find that when in different places, it is most convenient to pick different systems. But then, it becomes important to know how these systems are related where they overlap, so that you can stitch together a complete atlas of your manifold.

In the case of General Relativity, it is customary to use Minkowski coordinates in which time is imaginary.

Now we can sensibly ask, what shape is spacetime? Is it infinite or finite, open or closed? Might it be more like a hosepipe, with infinite time but finite space, or like a giant soap film with infinite space but finite time? All of these and more may be found as solutions to Einstein's equations. But they have one awkward omission.

It is easy enough to talk of the Big Bang, an apparent bounding point where time begins. But General Relativity does not deal in boundaries. Or at least, they are more boundaries to the theory, what are called boundary conditions, than to the spacetime it is describing. Physicists talk of the theory "breaking down" at such points. With no theory left of the physics at such boundaries, it is hard to believe the theorists who talk about what might or might not lie beyond. The Big Bang itself is one such boundary.

So far so good, Later I want to take a couple of diversions and come at the problem from a different angle. But first, there is a popular myth to expose.

Infinite Impossibility

A fair sprinkling of cosmologists like to believe that the Universe is infinite, and frequently tell the media so. They use it to justify wildly improbable, even patently absurd conclusions such as the existence of doppelgangers and Boltzmann brains. It is qute remarkable how seriously these things are peddled about by serious scientists who should know better. However there are deep problems with the whole idea.

The first is one of accepted wisdom, a fundamental principle of doing good science. No infinity has ever been observed in nature. They do tend to pop up in the maths, but scientists take this as a sure sign that the relevant equation has hit a "boundary condition", that the maths breaks down at this point and ceases to model reality (not that this stops it from being useful when kept away from the boudary). So there is something pretty dodgy about the claim that when it comes to the size of the Universe, we should ignore a fundamental principle of science. To the past mathematicians who realised this, such as Gauss and Hilbert, an infinite Universe was just a whimsy of Christian theology.

The second is one of logic and mathematics. It is often said that the universe was very small at the Big Bang. So let us follow that forward to today. Once it reached "the size of a grapefruit" it inflated faster-than-light, but still at a finite speed, for a finite length of time. It then settled down to a more leisurely expansion, for the next several billions of years. This is all finite. The only way it could have reached infinity by now is if it had been created in the Big Bang with infinite size in the first place.

One excuse offered for that inconsistency is, "I didn't mean mathematically infinite, I meant what mathematicians call arbitrarily large; just, way bigger than anything else we are considering." Well, you slightly forgot to make that clear. You also drew fancy conclusions from it that may be valid for mathematical infinites, but certainly are not for the merely arbitrarily large. In an infinite universe, even the wildly improbable will happen. But in an indefinitely large universe, the probabilities of your wacky phenomena are so even more indefinitely tiny that they sink orders of magnitude below the noise floor; they can never happen. And we know that infinities do not model reality. Your conclusions are inconsistent with your excuse.

Another common excuse is, "But I meant the observable universe was the size of a grapefruit." You are thus implying that the whole universe was created infinitely large at the Big Bang, only you forgot to note the fact. Unfortunately, it goes against all the scenarios examined in the relevant papers by Alan Guth and chums; there is not the slightest theoretical support for such a claim. It also poses something of a gross conceptual paradox: you cannot expand the infinitely large, mathematically it is still the same size afterwards as it was before. If it was already infinite then "expansion" has no meaning.

Yet another I have come across is, "No, our Universe may not be, but the higher-dimensional plenum it floats in sure is." Again, you slightly forgot to mention that your doppelgangers and spontaneously-erupting brains exist in other universes and not ours, and you forgot to criticise colleagues who do claim they exist in ours. That's surely the lamest excuse among three lame excuse.

We all know and laugh at the glib but absurd sophistry underlying Douglas Adams' infinite improbability drive. Yet all too often that same sophistry is peddled in all seriousness by theoretical physicists in their attempts to justify such things as Boltzmann brains or doppelganger universes. Douglas Adams was well aware of the smoke-and-mirrors nature of his fantasy; it is really rather disappointing that certain otherwise respectable physicists choose to forget.

So, having demolished our infinite improbability drivers, let's get back to doing proper science now.

Imaginary time

Stephen Hawking was among those who explored an alternative interpretation of General Relativity, in which Time is treated slightly differently. He called it "imaginary time" for technical but otherwise meaningless reasons, it is no more nor less in the imagination than "real time." In his model, the theory does not hit the buffers at the Big Bang but is able to negotiate smoothly around it. It's a bit like travelling north to the North Pole. Traditional Relativity breaks down when you reach the pole, because you cannot travel further north. But Hawking's version allows you to just keep on going, where you will find yourself now travelling back south again. He famously speculated that "perhaps the boundary condition of the Universe is that it has no boundary."

There is a mathematical subtlety built into this (See for example Yau 2010), though oddly I have never come across it in discussions of relativistic cosmology. A manifold such as a spacetime has two distinct kinds of property, global and local. Its global properties describe its shape in a general kind of way: is it bounded, does it have inherent loops or twists? For example the Klein bottle famously has a twist so that it has no "inside". The study of these properties is called topology. Local properties, the geometry, are more concerned with how far one point is from another, where it is most distorted, and suchlike. To study these local properties you typically have to lay down a coordinate system or metric and make a chart.

Relativity theory traditionally uses the coordinate system of Minkowski spacetime. Hawking's imaginary-time metric is subtly different but it can be overlaid onto the same topological manifolds as the conventional grid. There is generally little visible difference between them but, from the hints he gave, the two grids differ wildly around the Big Bang. So, it is unhelpful when cosmologists ramble cheerfully on about the beginning and end of the universe, without distinguishing between its assumed global properties and how the chosen local coordinate system relates to them. In particular, is the Big Bang singularity a boundary to the spacetime manifold or is it just an arbitrary "north pole", an artefact of pushing today's Minkowski chart too far back in time?

Metric signatures

The whole point of making time imaginary is that its mathematics behaves differently from ordinary "real" numbers. Then, once you have lots of dimensions, you will want to keep track of this behaviour. Recall that a coordinate system has a scale or metric as well as an origin and orientation. The imaginary treatment of one coordinate is an aspect of its metric, and we keep track of these imaginary dimensions by defining a "metric signature" for the geometry. By convention we use a + for an ordinary "real" dimension and a − for an imaginary one. (No, you can't add and subtract dimensions! The symbols may be stolen but their meanings are quite different) Thus, the metric signature of real three-dimensional space is simply +++, while that of Minkowski spacetime is +++−.

This at least is how physicists like it. But mathematically, there can be advantages in having a metric signature of −−−+, sometimes flipped to +−−−, which gives us a subtly different and in many ways more elegant algebra. It is that of special numbers called quaternions. Fortunately, there is an exact correspondence between the two algebras and so it is easy to convert the answers back to +++- when needed. Consequently, mathematicians such as Roger Penrose will often work with this signature.

Projective and complex spaces

Euclidean space is famous for having parallel lines. Given a plane on which are drawn a point, and a line not on that point, there is just one other line which passes through the point but does not meet the plane - a parallel line. But parallelism is not absolute as Euclid thought, we can have spaces with no parallels or with multiple lines through that point. The definition just given, of a line through a point, is known as Euclid's parallel postulate. By varying the postulate we obtain the various non-Euclidean spaces; more than one parallel through a point leads to hyperbolic spaces, no parallels leads to elliptic spaces. There is a fourth option, to simply abandon any kind of parallel postulate at all. This leads to projective geometries. Because they lack the complications of the extra restriction of parallelism they are the simplest and most elegant geometries. They can also be seen as containing the others, since the restrictions of parallelism ban certain constructions which are allowed in projective spaces. From the point of view of constructing the simplest and most elegant theory of reality possible, projective spaces (i.e. manifolds) are thus the obvious starting point.

A complex number is a number which is part real and part imaginary. A complex space has a metric with complex coordinates. The real and imaginary parts of each number are treated as separate coordinates or dimensions, just as say the x and y dimensions in the plane are. This leads to the awkwardness that a complex line, i.e. of one complex dimension, actually has two coordinate dimensions and we represent it as a real plane known as an Argand diagram (+− mapped onto ++). The phrase "complex plane" thus becomes ambiguous; does it mean the plane of the Argand diagram, a plane representing the complex line with metric signature +−, or does it mean a plane of two complex dimensions with metric signature ++−−? Mathematicians regularly tangle themselves up with this one, so I thought you'd better know. Thus a complex plane of two complex dimensions has four dimensions in all; it is a four-dimensional manifold. Similarly, complex three-space has the metric signature +++−−− and is a six-dimensional manifold. On the other hand a six-dimensional manifold with this signature may not be of three complex dimensions; there may be no such pairing between them and all six can be independent of each other; this happens for example in some string theories.

Throw in Hawking's use of time as inherently imaginary rather than needing a special geometry for it, and you have a large and complicated pool of metrics to play with, each with its accompanying distinct algebra. And it is about to get worse.

A curious property of projective spaces is that any real projective space with an even number of dimensions (i.e. of even dimension) is non-orientable; there is no global distinction between left- and right-handedness. On the other hand projective spaces of odd dimension and all complex spaces are, like all Euclidean spaces, orientable. Physicists find the maths of non-orientable spaces just too hard, so all their theories apply to orientable spaces. But what if the universe really is a projective space of even dimension? Such a space may perhaps be the simplest and most elegant, and therefore the most attractive, kind of space conceivable, but it is going to be a while before we can explore it as a possibility.

Things not bad enough for you yet? Then let's make them worse still.

Twistor space

Penrose is best remembered by physicists for his development of what is superficially a quite different kind of space, called twistor space.

Twistor space can be obtained by applying a mathematical operation known as a transform (specifically the Penrose-Ward transform) to conventional spacetime.

To get some idea of how the mathematics of a transform works, a simple example is the use of the Fourier transform for sound. If you watch a loudspeaker in slow-motion, you can see its cone moving in and out, creating a sound wave in the air. If you draw a graph of movement (amplitude) against time, it does indeed look like a wiggly wave. On the other hand, a typical sound comprises a spectrum of frequencies from deep bass through the mid-range to high treble. So we can also draw a graph of amplitude against frequency to obtain the sound spectrum. Early music synthesisers such as the Moog can create any given sound by generating all these individual frequencies and superimposing them, before feeding them to the loudspeaker as an electrical wave. The little hairs in our inner ear then pick out the individual frequencies of the spectrum and from that our brain creates an overall tonal quality or timbre for the sound. Neither the wave nor the spectrum is any more fundamental as a mathematical description, they both work and we simply use the description that most suits our purpose at the time. Mathematically, we can switch from the one description to the other using a Fourier transform. So it is with conventional spacetime and twistor space, via the Penrose-Ward transform.

Twistor space is a complex three-space, meaning it has six dimensions with the metric signature +++−−−. Remarkably (at least for me), twistor space is also a projective space (and therefore orientable).

Even more remarkably for physicists, calculations of certain quantum particle interactions and the probable outcomes (scattering amplitudes) are far more elegant and easier to solve in twistor space than in conventional spacetime. There is even a close relationship, via the Penrose-Ward transform, between twistor and string theories, where strings typically involve tightly-closed Calabi-Yau manifolds, also of metric signature +++−−−. But few if any of these are projective, and again, adding in the four dimensions of spacetime (and possibly another for luck) leaves the question of orientability open.

Oops!

All this appears immensely beguiling, the mathematical elegance is stunning and any variance from it almost unacceptable by definition. The next question must surely be, if twistor space is just a six-manifold with a funny metric, what shape is it?

Here, we reach an impasse. Twistor space simply does not fit with Relativity. Putting massive objects into it doesn't just bend the mathematics, it breaks it. All those particle-interaction shortcuts only work when energies are so high that the particle mass is irrelevant and we can ignore it. We have absolutely no idea how to tackle the problem.

Another loose end is the prediction by twistor-string theory of a supersymmetry between fundamental particles - where are all those supersymmetric partners? The Large Hadron Collider has ruled out most of the plausible options.

The answer will probably involve the fabled Grand Unification of gravity and quantum physics, which in turn will depend on adding in the "dark energy" behind the expansion of the universe and the "dark matter" holding galaxies together so tightly. Perhaps then we will we be able to reconcile twistor theory with massive particles and then pass it through something like a modified Penrose-Ward transform. And until that is done, we may never know what shape the universe is.

Bibliography

Updated 8 Feb 2024